Chapter 3

Seeing

3. Figure 2: Necker cube. Cover the painted cubes and Stare at the Necker cube for a while. You will notice, after a while, that its orientation inverts. Interestingly, your brain only sees, or rather prefers to see, one orientation at a time. You can find more examples of visual illusions like this on the internet.

Still on his voyage towards discovering the neural correlates of consciousness, Crick temporarily drops anchor on the sense of vision, with hopes to dig up recursive patterns of the underlying biology of this phenomenon. He offers penetrating questions and insights on how we see, highlighting that our vision is not only ambiguous; it can be deceitful, and it is a highly constructive process. In normal parlance, seeing is believing. However, as he continues landing assault on our confidence of how we, as laymen, think we see, one finishes the chapter with the impression that maybe believing is seeing. Being one of the most investigated biological systems, he points out that there is a lot of scientific information on vision; how light enters the eye, lands on the retina, and is transported to the brain via the optic nerve. However, a paradox exists; we have a lot of information on how we see, but we have no idea how we see. His hypothesis; “it’s all done by neurons”, leads him to believe that understanding this phenomenon will be translatable to an understanding of consciousness as well.


What you will learn: You do not see what is there; you see what your brain believes is there. Your vision is not as accurate nor as passive a process as it appears. Seeing is not like watching television, the brain actively seeks to interpret the information coming in and most of it is ambiguous. You will also learn some fascinating facts about how vision is not as reliable a sense as it appears.

How do you see something? You might not have given it much thought before, not even when taking an eye exam. Why would you—or anyone for that matter— question such a highly self-evident experience? A sense with such perspicuity seduces our intuitions into convictions about its accuracy; we think what we see is what is actually there, as we see it. But is it? Crick starts off the chapter by revealing how oblivious and disinterested the lay person is about how vision works. The question, "How does my brain work when I see something?", although simple, reveals itself to have a gluttonous appetite for a complex diet of information from psychology, physiology, and molecular and cell biology. Despite all this information, Crick emphasizes a paradoxical point; we still have no idea how we see anything. 

With such a surfeit of information failing to provide an adequate answer, one begins to get the impression that– whatever answer lies behind the question, "How do I see an apple?"– that answer contradicts the principles of Occam's razor. To demonstrate how interesting vision is, and the difficulty in fully understanding how it works, Crick initially presents three surprising aspects on the present (at the time) knowledge of the visual system; 

i. knowledge on it was enormous: knowledge accumulated over years from experiments, and theoretical work—involving both animals and humans—was significant.  As previously mentioned, disparate fields had made significant contributions and progress in understanding how vision works. In the psychology of vision, for example, different conditions under which the rapid succession of still pictures produced smooth movement had been probed and elucidated. Further, in the physiology of vision; the structure, behavior of the eye, and relevant parts of the brain had been parsed and understood. Lastly, in the molecular and cell biology of vision, the nerve cells and their constituent molecules had also been described. Such knowledge, by scientific standards, was extensive.

ii. Still, in spite of all that progress, no one–scientists and psychologists included–had a clear idea on how we see anything.  The simplest question: "How do I see color", still lacked an answer. What are the processes involved when one recalls the image of a familiar face, a familiar movie? Such questions, according to Crick, could not even be outlined with the current (at the time) knowledge on vision.

iii. How you think you see things is largely simplistic, or in many cases, plain wrong. Many of us have had our intuitions on vision contaminated by watching television. It is tempting to think that our vision works similarly to television i.e. our eyes are the camera and they project what is happening on to the retina, which acts like a screen. We, the viewers, watch this screen and are able to tell what is going on in the world. The viewer, in most cases, is a little man or woman somewhere inside our brain who is following what is going on, just like someone sitting in a cinema watching a movie. Crick calls this the Fallacy of the Homunculus (homunculus is Latin for "little man"). 

Interestingly, Crick admits that the Fallacy of the Homunculus requires an explanation, since seemingly everyone feels this way about how they see the world. However, before expounding on its mysterious existence and origins, he provides his Astonishing Hypothesis as a counter argument against it; "it's all done by neurons". With the Astonishing Hypothesis in mind, the problem of seeing —according to Crick—starts looking somewhat different. He states that the task then becomes more about finding brain operations or brain structures that work in an analogous manner to the mental picture of the homunculus. But before setting out to uncovering what they are, he first describes the brain and what the act of seeing entails. 

To the lay person, an even more ignored or absurd question compared to "How do you see anything?", is the question of "Why do you need to see anything?". One can only imagine the amusing responses to such questions, ranging from a simple "I just open my eyes''  to the more insightful ''To know what I am looking at". However, the answer to the need for vision is more nuanced than it appears. A global and biological reason is to increase survival and leave descendants for the continuation of the species. However, Crick adds that the primary function of vision has to do with addressing proximal goals. You need to know what is in front of you so you can decide, in real time, what to do about it. This holds great significance for both predators and prey in the animal kingdom, particularly in the context of the wild. He mentions that according to John Allman, a neurobiologist at Caltech, mammals—unlike reptiles, have a more pronounced need to preserve heat due to their constant activity and high body temperatures. This becomes even more important for smaller mammals, who have a much larger surface area relative to their volume i.e. they lose heat easily. Partly due to this, mammals had to be smarter in order to be able to quickly locate food. This required not only development of a larger neocortex, but also an increase in visual acuity. However, he states that most mammals do not have especially good vision, except the primates (monkeys, apes and humans). 

In order to derive meaning from the light entering your eyes as you gaze at an object before you, your eyes must possess the ability to perceive the wavelength, intensity, and motion of that light. With these parameters, the goal is to find out not only what is out there, but also what it is doing, and/or what it is likely to do. This requires experience and prior knowledge, most of the time. Three general remarks that Crick makes to set the stage so that we can understand just how vision works:


Taking these three remarks into account, along with the information they have provided, Crick stresses an important point about vision; What you see is not what is really there; it is what your brain believes is there. So maybe, a little skepticism (although not practical in everyday life) about what is in front of you is something that needs to be considered. How then do we actually see?


Just as a movie in a computer is not stored inside a computer as the movie one watches upon pressing "play", what we see with our eyes cannot be stored inside neurons as small pieces of visual scenes. Computers use symbols i.e. a combination of 0's and 1's to store and represent information. Using this analogy, Crick suggests that what we see as images and motion pictures is also represented and stored as symbols in our brains. As symbols, the brain can manipulate and store the information about objects at many different levels, and bring about the symbolic representation of that object when that particular object has been encountered. This is not a straightforward manner, and requires processing at multiple levels of the brain and corroboration from other senses, as we have seen. As Crick puts it, when something has been symbolized explicitly, the information can easily be made available so that it can be used, either for further processing or for action. So, how would vision work? By having neurons firing in a way that symbolizes such information fairly directly. Just as computers have a particular arrangement of 0s and 1s for each specific object, specific neurons firing in a specific way can be the way that our brains represent, and those objects. Such a process requires explicit multi-level, symbolic interpretations of the visual scene in order to "see" it. 



In summary, firing of a neuron (or neurons) is highly correlated with some particular aspect of the visual world. 


Blogger’s thoughts: So far this has been the most interesting chapter for me, because I have personally grappled with this topic for the past two or three years. Not only does Crick make the case that vision is elusive and deceptive, he states towards the end that there is no way for us to confirm that what we see is indeed veridical. Taking this to its logical conclusion, as Donald Hoffman has, you do not see reality. Had I not read "The Case Against Reality" by Donald Hoffman, I would have found this chapter to be mind boggling. In the book, Donald Hoffman goes a step beyond what Crick is saying here. According to Donald Hoffman, whatever reality is, it is not what you see. What you see is just an adaptive fiction. Worse than that, you do not even have the ability to see reality, even with all the current tools and technology. I still have not encountered a more radical view in all of science, and that is saying a lot. I highly recommend his book. Maybe I should review it next. Let me know. 


It is interesting to know that Crick and Hoffman had a discussion about the relationship between vision, veridicality, and the existence of reality, with Crick standing his ground that even though we cannot see reality, it exists and we have ways of knowing that it exists. This whole chapter reminded me of the argument of whether or not a falling tree makes a sound when no one is there to hear it. When you think of what sound is —vibrations in the air that propagate to your eardrums, then one gets a little uncomfortable talking about sound when there are no eardrums present to detect it, and brains to interpret it. One can go a step further and imagine being in a comma for two years and having the longest dream while in that comma. How would you know that you are not in actual reality? What is reality exactly, when you can have experiences in your brain and your body treats them as real? I guess, even in Science, one cannot totally avoid referencing The Matrix. 


With regards to how we see, I do not see how Crick's methodology is any different from that of other neuroscientists at the time. They had traced the sequence of events as light entered the eye to the retina and to the brain. I am guessing Crick will focus more on the particular firing sequence of neurons and the order in which they do so. But even so, fMRI had already been invented four years prior to Crick releasing the book. fMRI allows us to visualize the activity of neurons, in real time, as subjects perform certain tasks e.g. looking at images. With that, the activity of the neurons at certain brain regions can be identified and associated with certain states of consciousness. Let us not rush, maybe things will be clear as we delve into Chapter 4. Read on.....

←Chapter 1:Introduction - Review

←Chapter 2: The General Nature of Consciousness - Review

Chapter 4: The Psychology of Vision - Review→